Top Qs
Timeline
Chat
Perspective

Well-ordering principle

Statement that all non empty subsets of positive numbers contains a least element From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Remove ads

In mathematics, the well-ordering principle, also called the well-ordering property[1] or least natural number principle,[2][3] states that every non-empty subset of the nonnegative integers[4] contains a least element,[5] also called a smallest element.[6] In other words, if is a nonempty subset of the nonnegative integers, then there exists an element of which is less than, or equal to, any other element of .[1] Formally, .[7] Most sources state this as an axiom or theorem about the natural numbers, but the phrase "natural number" was avoided here due to ambiguity over the inclusion of zero. The statement is true about the set of natural numbers regardless whether it is defined as (nonnegative integers) or as (positive integers), since one of Peano's axioms for , the induction axiom (or principle of mathematical induction), is logically equivalent to the well-ordering principle.[8] Since and the subset relation is transitive, the statement about is implied by the statement about .

Experience with numbers favors this principle. For instance, the set T = {5, 8, 3, 11} has 3 as its least element, and 2 is the least element in the set of even positive numbers. It is a deceptively obvious principle because in many cases it is not clear what the least number actually is.

Lars Tuset, Abstract Algebra via Numbers[4]

The standard order on is well-ordered by the well-ordering principle, since it begins with a least element, regardless whether it is 1 or 0. By contrast, the standard order on (or on ) is not well-ordered by this principle, since there is no smallest negative number.[9] According to Deaconu and Pfaff,[10] the phrase "well-ordering principle" is used by some (unnamed) authors as a name for Zermelo's "well-ordering theorem" in set theory, according to which every set can be well-ordered. This theorem, which is not the subject of this article, implies that "in principle there is some other order on which is well-ordered, though there does not appear to be a concrete description of such an order."[9]

Remove ads

Equivalent to induction

The well-ordering principle is logically equivalent to the principle of mathematical induction, according to which .[11][12][13] In other words, if one takes the principle of mathematical induction as an axiom, one can prove the well-ordering principle as a theorem (as done in [14][15][16]), and conversely, if one takes the well-ordering principle as an axiom, one can prove the principle of mathematical induction as a theorem (as done in [17][18][19]).[11][12] The former is more common due to tradition, since the principle of mathematical induction was one of Peano's axioms for the natural numbers, and Peano was an influential mathematician.

The principle of mathematical induction and the well-ordering principle are each also equivalent to the principle of strong induction (also called the principle of complete induction), according to which .[20] Accordingly, one can also use the principle of strong induction as an axiom to prove the well-ordering principle as a theorem (as done in [21][22][23][24]), or take the well-ordering principle as an axiom to prove the principle of strong induction as a theorem (as in [25][a]).

This also means that, in axiomatic set theory, the definition of the natural numbers as the smallest inductive set, , is equivalent to the statement that the well-ordering principle is true for it.[8]

Remove ads

Implied by completeness of the reals

If one knows, as an axiom or theorem, that the real numbers are complete, then one can use this to prove the well-ordering principle for nonnegative integers.[28] This is because the completeness property implies that every bounded-from-below subset of has an infimum, which means that, since is a bounded-from-below subset of (and the subset relation is transitive), then also every set has an infimum , which implies that there exists an integer such that lies in the half-open interval , which implies that and .[29]

Remove ads

Nonalgebraic

The well-ordering principle, like the least upper bound axiom for real numbers,[30][31] is non-algebraic, i.e., it cannot be deduced from the algebraic properties of the integers (which form an ordered integral domain).[32][33]

Used in proofs by minimal counterexample

Summarize
Perspective

The well-ordering principle is used in proofs by minimal counterexample, also known light-heartedly as the "minimal criminal" method of proof,[34] in which to prove that every natural number belongs to a specified set , one assumes the contrary, which implies that the set of counterexamples is non-empty and thus (given the well-ordering principle) contains a smallest counterexample. One then shows that, for any counterexample, there is a still smaller counterexample, producing a contradiction. This mode of argument is the contrapositive of proof by complete induction, and is similar in its nature to Fermat's method of "infinite descent". The following are examples of this that have been found in the literature.

Example: no integer between 0 and 1

Theorem: There is no integer between 0 and 1, so that 1 is the smallest positive integer.

Proof.[35][36] Assume, for contradiction, that there exists an integer such that . By the well-ordering principle, the set of positive integers less than 1 has a least element, say . Since , multiplying all parts of the inequality by gives . But if is an integer, then would also be an integer, which contradicts the initial assumption that was the least positive integer between 0 and 1. Therefore, this assumption is false, and there is no integer between 0 and 1.

Example: all decreasing nonnegative integer sequences finite

Theorem: Every decreasing sequence of nonnegative integers is finite.

Proof.[37][38] Suppose that there exists a strictly decreasing sequence of nonnegative integers ; then by the well-ordering principle, has a least element for some . But must be the last in the sequence, otherwise , which contradicts the assumption that is the smallest member.

Example: prime factorization

Theorem: Every integer greater than one is a product of finitely many primes. This theorem constitutes part of the Fundamental Theorem of Arithmetic.

Proof.[39][40][41] Let be the set of all integers greater than one that cannot be factored as a product of primes. We show that is empty: assume for the sake of contradiction that is not empty. Then, by the well-ordering principle, there is a least element ; cannot be prime since a prime number itself is considered a length-one product of primes. By the definition of non-prime numbers, has factors , where are integers greater than one and less than . Since , they are not in as is the smallest element of . So, can be factored as products of primes, where and , meaning that , a product of primes. This contradicts the assumption that , so the assumption that is nonempty must be false.

Remove ads

Notes

  1. Gallier is the only source which explicitly uses the well-ordering principle to directly prove the principle of complete induction, although even Gallier does not take the well-ordering principle as an axiom, but rather proves it as a theorem from the principle of mathematical induction. See also [18], where strong induction is a corollary of the proof of strong induction from the well-ordering principle; or [26], where strong induction is proved equivalent to the well-ordering principle; or [27], where the equivalence of the three principles is proved by showing that the principle of induction implies the principle of strong induction, the principle of strong induction implies the well-ordering principle, and the well-ordering principle implies the principle of induction.
Remove ads

References

Loading related searches...

Wikiwand - on

Seamless Wikipedia browsing. On steroids.

Remove ads